The use of the kants principle in the three approaches to environmental ethics

Yet, in addition to any such value, it is normally said that a person, as a person, has intrinsic value, i.

Environmental Ethics

What we would not have yet is a full account of right action. For instance, Callicott maintains that if culling a white-tailed deer is necessary for the protection of the holistic biotic good, then it is a land-ethical requirement to do so. The idea here is to reject a subjectivism about the good, holding that what makes it true that something is good is not that it stands in some relation to desire but rather that it is somehow perfective or completing of a being, where what is perfective or completing of a being depends on that being's nature.

Our welfare depends on breathable air, drinkable water and edible food. How can we come to know these fundamental goods.

This video is unavailable.

It commands no respect, reverence or love. An important message underlying the debate, perhaps, is that even if ecological restoration is achievable, it might have been better to have left nature intact in the first place.

Kantian ethics

He rests this second project on the position that we — or at least creatures with rational wills — possess autonomy. Hence, together with the distinction between perfect and imperfect duties, Kant recognized four categories of duties: Kant held that ordinary moral thought recognized moral duties toward ourselves as well as toward others.

Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. If their value thereby becomes the source of the rightness of our actions — say, our actions are right if and because they treat that self-standing value in various ways — then her reading too is teleological.

Catholic University of America Press. According to Libertarians the second law is the only law that should exist. In this case, it is the goodness of the character of the person who does or would perform it that determines the rightness of an action. But the method approach has the advantage of firmly rooting natural law arguments for moral principles in the goods the pursuit of which those moral principles are supposed to regulate.

In other words, if a person's emotions or desires cause them to do something, then that action cannot give them moral worth. These topics, among others, are addressed in central chapters of the second Critique, the Religion and again in the Metaphysics of Morals, and are perhaps given a sustained treatment in Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View.

Kant's Three Principles of Morality

Many see it as introducing more of a social dimension to Kantian morality. For instance, act consequentialism is one sort of teleological theory. However, the critical theorists argue that the positivistic disenchantment of natural things and, likewise, of human beings—because they too can be studied and manipulated by science disrupts our relationship with them, encouraging the undesirable attitude that they are nothing more than things to be probed, consumed and dominated.

He argues that a dutiful action from any of these motives, however praiseworthy it may be, does not express a good will. Altman gestures towards a Hegelian account of corporate moral responsibility p. Respect for such laws could hardly be thought valuable.

The Natural Law Tradition in Ethics

Cohen believes that even when humans are not rational because of age such as babies or fetuses or mental disability, agents are still morally obligated to treat them as an ends in themselves, equivalent to a rational adult such as a mother seeking an abortion.

It also remains unclear in what sense rivers, mountains and forests can be regarded as possessors of any kind of interests. In Chapter 1, Altman argues that we have obligations to be concerned for the well-being of animals because cruelty or indifference to the suffering of animals corrupts our character and makes us more likely to be cruel to human rational agents.

However, because of the varieties of, and disagreements among, feminist theories, the label may be too wide to be informative and has generally fallen from use. The Challenge of Environmental Ethics Suppose putting out natural fires, culling feral animals or destroying some individual members of overpopulated indigenous species is necessary for the protection of the integrity of a certain ecosystem.

The three schools are virtue ethics, consequentialist ethics, and deontological or duty-based ethics. Each approach provides a different way to understanding ethics. ‘Natural law theory’ is a label that has been applied to theories of ethics, theories of politics, theories of civil law, and theories of religious morality.

This is the second reason Kant held that fundamental issues in ethics must be addressed with an a priori method: The ultimate subject matter of ethics is the nature and content of the principles that necessarily determine a rational will. Approaches to Environmental Ethics.

Dr DeWeese gives an introduction to the four most common approaches to Environmental Ethics and explains that all four are flawed theologically as they are centered on God. Here, however, Kant would support GM crops if the company made a way for all farmers to be able to use them.

Recycling – Prevents waste of materials, reduces consumption and pollution in making new materials Synthetic A Priori For many ethicists, environmental ethics is about weighing the cost and the benefit of our proposed actions. Kant's Principle and Environmental Ethics 1.

All of the three approaches to environmental ethics use Kant's principle to various extents. The differences between them lie in their individual definitions of moral categories.

The use of the kants principle in the three approaches to environmental ethics
Rated 4/5 based on 41 review
Kant's Moral Philosophy (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)